Discover
/
Article

Discrete or Continuous?: The Quest for Fundamental Length in Modern Physics

JAN 01, 2015

DOI: 10.1063/PT.3.2657

Luis J. Garay

Discrete or Continuous?: The Quest for Fundamental Length in Modern Physics, Amit Hagar, Cambridge U. Press, 2014. $90.00 (267 pp.). ISBN 978-1-107-06280-1 Buy at Amazon

For Isaac Newton, space and time were independent, continuous entities. Albert Einstein unified the two into spacetime, again a continuous object. With the development of quantum field theory, however, physicists began to take seriously the idea that discreteness might be an essential component of our understanding of space and time. Amit Hagar’s Discrete or Continuous? The Quest for Fundamental Length in Modern Physics takes the reader on an enjoyable journey—by turns historical, philosophical, and physical—in a quest to unravel many of the subtleties that underlie the concept of a minimum length in physics.

PTO.v68.i1.44_1.d1.jpg

One central question explored in the book is whether the concept of spacetime can emerge solely from microscopic dynamics or whether, on the contrary, at least some primitive geometric notions are necessary. Also of paramount importance to the author—and also to me and, I dare say, many other physicists—are empirical data that support the existence of a minimum length in physical processes. That requirement has two aspects to it. On the one hand, the changes that a minimum length would introduce must agree with current experiments and observations within the accuracy of today’s data. That is just a consistency check. On the other hand, any pet microscopic theory must make falsifiable predictions that entail deviations from continuum behavior. Without those two empirical points being satisfied, a theory of minimum length does not leave the realm of metaphysics. And although empirical confirmations or falsifications are common to most scientific quests, they (and in particular, the need to make predictions) were historically often left aside when dealing with the microscopic structure of spacetime. But that is not so anymore, and Hagar stresses the community’s new attitude in his final chapter.

Aimed at theoretical physicists and philosophers of science, Discrete or Continuous? contains eight chapters and a coda, in the form of questions and answers, that superbly summarizes the main issues discussed in the body of the text. After the introduction, chapters 2 and 3 deal with the mathematical and philosophical aspects of spacetime discreteness, or minimum length. The author concludes that neither mathematics nor philosophy precludes spacetime having a discrete nature. He also points out that a minimum length may appear in two different forms. The first is ontological—a minimum size for the building blocks of a truly discrete spacetime. The second has an epistemological character, a limitation in our capability to acquire knowledge, without any implication concerning the nature of spacetime.

Chapters 4 and 5 present in great detail a plethora of early proposals for a minimum length. Those early ideas were generally in the context of quantum gravitational or semiclassical analyses—in which case the minimum length was the Planck length—or were suggested as a means to eliminate divergences in quantum field theories at small scales. Chapter 6 analyzes a possible dynamical origin for geometrical concepts, mainly based on correspondence between Albert Einstein and W. F. G. Swann in the 1940s. Together, those three chapters provide a wonderful and insightful historical presentation on many of the ideas entertained by the brightest minds in 20th-century theoretical physics. It is a section that no practitioner should do without.

Current attempts to quantize gravity are described in chapter 7. It offers a brief account of the most popular theories and approaches, although, in my opinion, a somewhat superficial one for the task at hand, at least in comparison with previous chapters. Included therein are discussions of string theory, loop quantum gravity, emergent gravity, and other interesting proposals relevant to the discrete-versus-continuous debate. Throughout, Hagar emphasizes the primacy of geometry over dynamics.

Chapter 8 is an account of the current situation of quantum gravitational theories in the empirical arena, and in particular it concerns four principles that have guided theoretical physics for years: locality, causality, unitarity, and local Lorentz invariance. The message of the chapter, and indeed of the whole book, is summarized in the last sentence: “If, like me, one requires more than mere consistency proofs, since it seems that only new predictions will be able to decide the issue and to convince supporters of the continuum to abandon their view, then, I am afraid, we still have a long way to go.”

More about the Authors

Luis Garay is a professor of physics at the Complutense University of Madrid in Spain. He conducts research at the interface of gravity and quantum theory, including black holes and studies of a minimum length in gravitational physics.

This Content Appeared In
pt_cover0115.jpg

Volume 68, Number 1

Related content
/
Article
Immeasurable Weather: Meteorological Data and Settler Colonialism from 1820 to Hurricane Sandy, Sara J. Grossman
/
Article
/
Article
Predicting Our Climate Future: What We Know, What We Don’t Know, and What We Can’t Know, David Stainforth
/
Article
/
Article
/
Article
Physics of Wave Turbulence, Sébastien Galtier

Get PT in your inbox

Physics Today - The Week in Physics

The Week in Physics" is likely a reference to the regular updates or summaries of new physics research, such as those found in publications like Physics Today from AIP Publishing or on news aggregators like Phys.org.

Physics Today - Table of Contents
Physics Today - Whitepapers & Webinars
By signing up you agree to allow AIP to send you email newsletters. You further agree to our privacy policy and terms of service.